Did you know ... | Search Documentation: |
Pack narsese -- jmc/selfaware.md |
NOTES ON SELF-AWARENESS
John McCarthy
Computer Science Department
Stanford University
Stanford, CA 94305
jmc@cs.stanford.edu
http://www-formal.stanford.edu/jmc/
2004 Apr 11, 10:41 p.m.
Abstract
These notes discuss self-awareness in humans and machines. The
goal is to determine useful forms of machine self-awareness and also
those that are on the road to human-level AI.
This is a draft which is to be improved, and suggestions are so-
licited. There are a few formulas in this version. The final version will
have more.
1 Introduction
Developing self-aware computer systems will be an interesting and challeng-
ing project.
It seems to me that the human forms of self-awareness play
an important role in humans achieving our goals and will also be impor-
tant for advanced computer systems. However, I think they will be difficult
to implement in present computer formalisms, even in the most advanced
logical AI formalisms. The useful forms of computer agent self-awareness
will not be identical with the human forms.
Indeed many aspects of hu-
man self-awareness are bugs and will not be wanted in computer systems.
(McCarthy 1996) includes a discussion of this and other aspects of robot
consciousness.
Nevertheless, for now, human self-awareness, as observed introspectively
is the best clue.
Introspection may be more useful than the literature of
experimental psychology, because it gives more ideas, and the ideas can be
checked for usefulnes by considering programs that implement them. More-
over, at least in the beginning of the study of self-awareness, we should be
ontologically promiscuous, e.g. we should not identify intentions with goals
Significant differences may become apparent, and we can always squeeze
later. 1
Some human forms of self-awareness are conveniently and often linguisti-
cally expressed and others are not. For example, one rarely has occasion to
announce the state of tension in ones muscles. However, something about it
can be expressed if useful. How the sensation of blue differs from the sen-
sation of red apparently cannot be verbally expressed. At least the qualia-
oriented philosophers have put a lot of effort into saying so. What an artificial
agent can usefully express in formulas need not correspond to what humans
ordinarily say, or even can say. In general, computer programs can usefully
be given much greater powers of self-awareness than humans have, because
every component of the state of the machine or its memory can be made
accessible to be read by the program.
A straightforward way of logically formalizing self-awareness is in terms
of a mental situation calculus with certain observable fluents. The agent
is aware of the observable mental fluents and their values. A formalism
with mental situations and fluents will also have mental events including
actions, and their occurrence will affect the values of the observable fluents.
I advocate the form of situation calculus proposed in (McCarthy 2002).
Self-awareness is continuous with other forms of awareness. Awareness of
being hot and awareness of the room being hot are similar. A simple fluent of
which a person is aware is hunger. We can write Hungry(s) about a mental
situation s, but we write Holds(Hungry, s), then Hungry can be the value
of bound variables.. Anohter advantage is that now Hungry is an object,
and the agent can compare Hungry with T hirsty or Bored. I’m not sure
where the object Hunger comes in, but I’m pretty sure our formalism should
have it and not just Hungry. We can even use Holds(Applies(Hunger, I), s)
1Some philosophers who emphasize qualia may be inclined to regard self-awareness as
a similar phenomenon—in which a person has an undifferentiated awareness of self, like
the qualia oriented notion of the pure sensation of red as distinct from blue. This is not
at all what is needed for AI. Rather we study the specific aspects of self and its activity
which it is useful to be aware.
but tolerate abbreviations, especially in contexts. 2 3 4
Our goal in this research is an epistemologically adequate formalism in the
sense of (McCarthy and Hayes 1969) for representing what a person or robot
can actually learn about the world. In this case, the goal is to represent facts
of self-awareness of a system, both as an internal language for the system
and as an external language for the use of people or other systems.
Basic entities, e.g. automaton states as discussed in (McCarthy and Hayes 1969)or neural states may be good for devising theories at present, but we cannot
express what a person or robot actually knows about its situation in such
terms.
2 Of what are we aware, and of what should
computers be aware?
Humans are aware of many different aspects of their minds. Here are samples
of kinds of self-awareness—alas not a classification.
2The English grammatical form ”I am hungry” has no inevitability to it. French has
”J’ai faim”, literally ”I have hunger”, and German has ”Es hungert mich”, literally ”It
hungers me”. In French the noun ”faim” meaning ”hunger” is used, whereas in English an
adjective “hungry” is used. In logical we have both; I don’t see a use for a logical version
of the German form.
3Holds(Hungry(I), s) might be written if our agent needs to compare its hunger with
that of other agents. However, if we use formalized contexts ((McCarthy 1993)) we can get
by with Holds(Hungry, s) in an inner context in which the sentences are about the agent’s
self. We won’t use formalized contexts in these notes, but an informal notion of context
can avoid some worries. For example, some discussions are carried out entirely in contexts
in which the fact that John McCarthy is a professor at Stanford is permanent. However,
when needed, this context can be transcended. Likewise there are useful time-limited
contexts in which George W. Bush is permanently President of the United States.
4In spite of the fact that English has an enormous vocabulary, the same word is used
with diverse meanings. I don’t speak of simple homonyms like ”lock on a door” and ”lock
of hair”. These can be ruthlessly eliminated from our computer language, e.g. by having
words lock1 and lock2. A more interesting example is that one can speak of knowing a
person, knowing a fact, and knowing a telephone number. German uses kennen for the
first and wissen for the second; I don’t know about the third. In my (McCarthy 1979),
”First order theories of individual concepts and propositions”, I use different words for
the different concepts. I suspect that it will be useful to tolerate using the same term in
related senses, e.g. using the same word for the bank as an institution and as a building,
because too many related meanings will arise.
Thus I am human like other humans.
[I am a small child, and I am
”supposed to do” what the others are doing. This is innate or learned
very early on the basis of an innate predisposition to learn it.5
What might we want an artificial agent to know about the fact that it
is one among many agents? It seems to me that the forms in which self-
awareness develops in babies and children are likely to be particularly
suggestive for what we will want to build into computers.
is the fact to be represented?
It helps to organize as much as possible of a system’s knowledge as
knowledge of permanent entities.
process and also of its future. Awareness of its present depends on
some concept of the “extended now”.
Temporary phenomena
I want to be healthy,
wealthy and wise. I want to marry Yumyum and plan to persuade her
guardian Koko to let me.
won’t.
5Autistic children may be deficient in this respect.
you do you are likely to end up distinguishing a particular kind of goal
corresponding to what the unsophisticated call an intention.
Hayes.
hopes, fears, goals, expectations, anti-expectations, intentions action:
predict, want to know, promises and commitments.
Attitudes toward the past:
regrets, satisfactions, counterfactuals
I’m aware that I regret having offended him. I believe that if I hadn’t
done so, he would have supported my position in this matter. It looks
like a belief is a kind of weak awareness.
Attitudes to the present:
satisfaction, I see a dog. I don’t see the dog. I wonder where the dog
has gone.
There are also attitudes toward timeless entities, e.g. towards kinds of
people and things. I like strawberry ice cream but not chocolate chip.
10. Hopes: A person can observe his hopes. I hope it won’t rain tomorrow.
Yesterday I hoped it wouldn’t rain today. I think it will be advanta-
geous to equip robots with mental qualities we can appropriately call
hopes.
11. Fears: I fear it will rain tomorrow.
Is a fear just the opposite of a
hope? Certainly not in humans, because the hormonal physiology is
different, but maybe we could design it that way in robots. Maybe, but
I wouldn’t jump to the conclusion that we should.
Why are hopes and fears definite mental objects? The human brain
is always changing but certain structures can persist. Specific hopes
and fears can last for years and can be observed.
It is likely to be
worthwhile to build such structures into robot minds, because they
last much longer than specific neural states.
12. An agent may observe that it has incompatible wants.
2.1 Mental actions
The companion of observation is action. A theory of self-awareness, i.e. of
mental observation, is complemented by a theory of mental action.
(McCarthy 1982) discusses heuristics for coloring maps with four colors.
A form of self-awareness is involved. In coloring a map of the United States,
the goal of coloring California can be postponed to the very end, because it
has only three neighbors and therefore no matter how the rest of the map
is colored, there will always be a color for California. Once California is
removed from the map, Arizona has only three neighbors. The postponement
process can be continued as long as possible. In the case of the US, all states
get postponed and then can be colored without backtracking. In general it
is often possible to observe that in planning a task, certain subtasks can be
postponed to the end. Thus postponement of goals is a mental action that
is sometimes useful.
A human-level agent, and even an agent of considerably lower level, has
policies. These are creatable, observable both in their structure and in their
actions, and changeable.
Useful actions: decide on an intention or a goal. Drop an intention.
Clearly there are many more mental actions and we need axioms describ-
ing their effects.
3 Machine self-awareness
Self-awareness is not likely to be a feasible or useful attribute of a program
that just computes an answer. It is more likely to be feasible and useful for
programs that maintain a persistent activity.
What kind of program would be analogous to Pat deciding while on the
way to his job that he needed cigarettes? See formula (4) below. Here are
some possibiliities.
It’s not clear what event in a computer program might correspond to
Pat’s sudden need for cigarettes. The following examples don’t quite make
it.
A specialized theorem-proving program T 1 is being operated as a sub-
program by a reasoning program T . Assume that the writer of T has only
limited knowledge of the details of T 1, because T 1 is someone else’s program.
T might usefully monitor the operation of T 1 and look at the collection of
intermediate results T 1 has produced. If too many of these are redundant,
T may restart T 1 with different initial conditions and with a restriction that
prevents sentences of a a certain form from being generated.
An operating system keeps track of the resources a user is using, and
check for attempts to use forbidden resources. In particular it might check
for generation of password candidates. In its present form this example may
bad, because we can imagine the checking be done by the programs that
implement supervisor calls rather than by an inspector operating with clock
interrupts. While the programs called by clock interrupts exhibit a simple
form of self-awareness, the applications I know about are all trivial.
The main technical requirement for self-awareness of ongoing processes
in computers is an interrupt system, especially a system that allows clock
interrupts. Hardware supporting interrupts is standard on all computers
today but didn’t become standard until the middle 1960s.6 The human
brain is not a computer that executes instructions in sequence and therefore
doesn’t need an interrupt system that can make it take an instruction out
of sequence. However, interruption of some kind is clearly a feature of the
brain.
With humans the boundary between self and non-self is pretty clear. It’s
the skin. With computer based systems, the boundary may be somewhat
arbitrary, and this makes distinguishing self-awareness from other awareness
arbitrary. I suppose satisfactory distinctions will become clearer with expe-
rience.
3.1 Interrupts, programming languages and self-awarenesConsider a persistent program driving a car that is subject to observation and
modification by a higher level program. We mentioned the human example of
noticing that cigarettes are wanted and available. The higher level program
must observe and modify the state of the driving program. It seems that a
6Historical note: The earliest interrupt system I know about was the “Real time pack-
age” that IBM announced as a special order instigated by Boeing in the late 1950s. Boeing
wanted it in order to control a wind tunnel using an IBM 704 computer. At M.I.T. we
also needed an interrupt system in order to experiment with time-sharing on the IBM 704.
We designed a simple one, but when we heard about the much better “Real time package”
we started begging for it. Begging from IBM took a while, but they gave it to us.
The earliest standard interrupt system was on the D.E.C. PDP-1 and was designed by
Ed Fredkin, then at Bolt, Beranek and Newman, who persuaded D.E.C. to include it in
the machine design. Again the purpose was time-sharing.
clock interrupt activating the higher level program is all we need from the
hardware.
We need considerably more from the software and from the programming
languages. A cursory glance at the interrupt handling facilities of C, Ada,
Java, and Forth suggests that they are suitable for handling interrupts of high
level processes by low level processes that buffer the transfer of information.
Lisp and Smalltalk can handle interrupts, but have no standard facilities.
My opinion, subject to correction, is that self-awareness of the kinds
proposed in this note will require higher level programming language facilities
whose nature may be presently unknown. They will be implemented by the
present machine language facilities.
However, one feature of Lisp, that programs are data, and their abstract
syntax is directly represented, is likely to be necessary for programs that
examine themselves and their subprograms. This feature of Lisp hasn’t been
much used except in macros and has been abandoned in more recent pro-
gramming languages—in my opinion mistakenly.
4 Formulas
Formalized contexts as discussed in (McCarthy 1993) will be helpful in ex-
pressing self-awareness facts compactly.
Pat is aware of his intention to eat dinner at home.
c(Awareness(P at)) : Intend(I, M od(At(Home), Eat(Dinner)))
or
Ist(Awareness(P at), Intend(I, M od(At(Home), Eat(Dinner))))
(1)
Here Awareness(P at) is a certain context. Eat(Dinner) denotes the
general act of eating dinner, logically different from eating Steak7642.
M od(At(Home), Eat(Dinner)) is what you get when you apply the modifier
“at home” to the act of eating dinner. I don’t have a full writeup of this
proposal for handling modifiers like adjectives, adverbs, and modifier clauses.
Intend(I, X) says that I intend X. The use of I is appropriate within the
context of a person’s (here Pat’s) awareness.
We should extend this to say that Pat will eat dinner at home unless his
intention changes. This can be expressed by formulas like
(2)
(3)
¬Ab17(P at, x, s)∧Intends(P at, Does(P at, x), s) → (∃s0 > s)Occurs(Does(P at, x), s).in the notation of (McCarthy 2002).
Here’s an example of awareness leading to action.
Pat is driving to his job. Presumably he could get there without much
awareness of that fact, since the drive is habitual. However, he becomes
aware that he needs cigarettes and that he can stop at Mac’s Smoke Shop
and get some. Two aspects of his awareness, the driving and the need for
cigarettes are involved. That Pat is driving to his job can be expressed with
varying degrees of elaboration. Here are some I have considered.
Driving(P at, J ob, s)
Doing(P at, Drive(J ob), s)
Holds(Doing(P at, M od(Destination(J ob), Drive)), s)
Holds(M od(Ing, M od(Destination(J ob, Action(Drive, P at))), s)
.
The last two use a notion like that of an adjective modifying a noun. Here’s
a simple sentence giving a consequence of Pat’s awareness. It uses Aware
as a modal operator. This may require repair or it may be ok in a suitably
defined context.
Aware(P at, Driving(J ob, s), s) ∧ Aware(P at, N eeds(Cigarettes)
, s)
∧Aware(P at, About-to-pass(CigaretteStore, s)
, s)
→ Occurs(StopAt(CigaretteStore), s).
(4)
The machine knows that if its battery is low, it will be aware of the fact.
Knows(M achine, (∀s0)(LowBattery(s0) → Aware(LowBattery(s0))), s)
(5)
The machine knows, perhaps because a sensor is broken, that it will not
necessarily be aware of a low battery.
Knows(M achine, ¬(∀s0)(LowBattery(s0) → Aware(LowBattery(s0))), s)
(6)
The positive sentence “I am aware that I am aware . . . ” doesn’t seem to
have much use by itself, but sentences of the form “If X happens, I will be
aware of Y” should be quite useful.
5 Miscellaneous
Here are some examples of awareness and considerations concerning aware-
ness that don’t yet fit the framework of the previous sections.
I am slow to solve the problem because I waste time thinking about ducks.
I’d like Mark Stickel’s SNARK to observe, “I’m slow to solve the problem,
because I keep proving equivalent lemmas over and over”.
I was aware that I was letting my dislike of the man influence me to reject
his proposal unfairly.
in making self-aware systems.
Here are some general considerations about what fluents should be used
adequacy as introduced in (McCarthy and Hayes 1969).
better turns up.”
Is there a technical difference between observations that constitute self-
observations and those that don’t? Do we need a special mechanism for
self-observation? At present I don’t think so.
If p is a precondition for some action, it may not be in consciousnes,
but if the action becomes considered, whether p is true will then come into
consciousnes, i.e. short term memory. We can say that the agent is subaware
of p.
What programming languages provide for interrupts?
References
McCarthy, J. 1979. Ascribing mental qualities to machines7. In M. Ringle
(Ed.), Philosophical Perspectives in Artificial Intelligence. Harvester Press.
Reprinted in (McCarthy 1990).
McCarthy, J. 1982. Coloring maps and the Kowalski doctrine8. Technical
Report STAN-CS-82-903, Dept Computer Science, Stanford University,
April. AIM-346.
McCarthy, J. 1990. Formalizing Common Sense: Papers by John Mc-
Carthy. Ablex Publishing Corporation.
McCarthy, J. 1993. Notes on Formalizing Context9. In IJCAI93.
McCarthy, J. 1996. Making Robots Conscious of their Mental States10.
In S. Muggleton (Ed.), Machine Intelligence 15. Oxford University Press.
Appeared in 2000. The web version is improved from that presented at
Machine Intelligence 15 in 1995.
McCarthy, J. 2002. Actions and other events in situation calculus11. In
B. S. A.G. Cohn, F. Giunchiglia (Ed.), Principles of knowledge represen-
tation and reasoning: Proceedings of the eighth international conference
(KR2002). Morgan-Kaufmann.
McCarthy, J., and P. J. Hayes. 1969. Some Philosophical Problems from
the Standpoint of Artificial Intelligence12. In B. Meltzer and D. Michie
(Eds.), Machine Intelligence 4, 463–502. Edinburgh University Press.
Reprinted in (McCarthy 1990).
/@steam.stanford.edu:/u/jmc/f03/selfaware.tex: begun Sun Oct 26 12:45:55 2003, latexed April 11, 2004 at 10:41 p.m.
7http://www-formal.stanford.edu/jmc/ascribing.html
8http://www-formal.stanford.edu/jmc/coloring.html
9http://www-formal.stanford.edu/jmc/context.html
10http://www-formal.stanford.edu/jmc/consciousness.html
11http://www-formal.stanford.edu/jmc/sitcalc.html
12http://www-formal.stanford.edu/jmc/mcchay69.html